References

Anstis, S. (1992). Visual adaptation to a negative, brightness-reversed world: Some preliminary observations. In G. Carpenter & S. Grossberg (Eds.) Neural networks for vision and image processing (pp. 1-14). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Ballard, D. H. (1991). Animate vision. Artificial Intelligence, 48 (1), 57-86. 10.1016/0004-3702(91)90080-4

Bar, M. (2003). A cortical mechanism for triggering top-down facilitation in visual object recognition. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 15 (4), 600-609. 10.1162/089892903321662976

Baron-Cohen, S. & Harrison, J. E. (Eds.) (1997). Synaesthesia: Classic and contemporary readings. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.

Baron-Cohen, S., Harrison, J., Goldstein, L. H. & Wyke, M. (1993). Coloured speech perception: Is synaesthesia what happens when modularity breaks down? Perception, 22 (4), 419-426. 10.1068/p220419

Baron-Cohen, S., Wyke, M. & Binnie, C. (1987). Hearing words and seeing colours: An experimental investigation of a case of synaesthesia. Perception, 16 (6), 761-767. 10.1068/p160761

Bayne, T. & Montague, M. (Eds.) (2011). Cognitive Phenomenology. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

Bayne, T. & Spener, M. (2010). Introspective humility. Philosophical Issues, 20 (1), 1-22. 10.1111/j.1533-6077.2010.00176.x

Bayne, T. (2009). Perception and the reach of phenomenal content. The Philosophical Quarterly, 59 (236), 385-404. 10.1111/j.1467-9213.2009.631.x

(2015). Introspective insecurity. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.) Open MIND. Frankfurt a. M., GER: MIND Group.

Belmore, S. C. & Shevell, S. K. (2011). Very-long-term and short-term chromatic adaptation: Are their influences cumulative? Vision Research, 51 (3), 362-366. 10.1016/j.visres.2010.11.011

Block, N. (1990). Inverted earth. Philosophical Perspectives, 4, 53-79. 10.2307/2214187

(2008). Consciousness and cognitive access. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 108, 289-317.

Bompas, A. & O’Regan, J. K. (2006a). Evidence for a role of action in color perception. Perception, 35 (1), 65-78. 10.1068/p5356

(2006b). More evidence for sensorimotor adaptation in color perception. Journal of Vision, 6 (2), 142-153. 10.1167/6.2.5

Bor, D., Billington, J. & Baron-Cohen, S. (2007). Savant memory for digits in a case of synaesthesia and Asperger syndrome is related to hyperactivity in the lateral prefrontal cortex. Neurocase, 13, 311-319. 10.1080/13554790701844945

Botvinick, M. & Cohen, J. (1998). Rubber hands “feel” touch that eyes see. Nature, 391 (756). 10.1038/35784

Braddon-Mitchell, D. & Jackson, F. (2007). Philosophy of mind and cognition. Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

Brentano, F. (1973). Embodied Prediction. In A. C. Rancurello, D. B. Terrell & L. L. McAlister (Eds.) (Trans.) London, UK: Routledge.

Briscoe, R. E. (2014). Do intentions for action penetrate visual experience? Frontiers in Psychology, 5 (1265). 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.01265

Broackes, J. (1992). The autonomy of color. In K. Lennon & D. Charles (Eds.) Reduction, explanation and realism (pp. 421-465). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

Brogaard, B. & Gatzia, D. E. (forthcoming). Is color experience cognitively penetrable? Topics in Cognitive Science: Special Issue on Cortical Color.

Brogaard, B., Vanni, S. & Silvanto, J. (2013). Seeing mathematics: Perceptual experience and brain activity in acquired synesthesia. Neurocase, 19, 566-575. 10.1080/13554794.2012.701646

Burge, T. (2010). Origins of objectivity. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

Butterfill, S. (2009). Seeing causes and hearing gestures. The Philosophical Quarterly, 59 (236), 405-428. 10.1111/j.1467-9213.2008.585.x

Byrne, A. & Hilbert, D. (Eds.) (1997). Readings on color, volume 1: The philosophy of color, Consciousness: Essays from a higher-order perspective. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

Carruthers, P. (2005). Conscious experience versus conscious thought. In P. Carruthers (Ed.) Consciousness: Essays from a Higher-Order Perspective. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

Casati, R. (1990). What is wrong in inverting spectra? Teoria, 10, 183-6.

Chalmers, D. (1996). The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

(2003). The content and epistemology of phenomenal belief. In Q. Smith & A. Jokic (Eds.) Consciousness: New philosophical perspectives (pp. 220-272). Oxford, UK: Oxford.

Churchland, P. (1985). Reduction, qualia, and direct introspection of brain states. Journal of Philosophy, 82 (1), 8-28. 10.2307/2026509

(1989). Knowing qualia: A reply to Jackson. In Y. Nagasawa, P. Ludlow & D. Stoljar (Eds.) A neurocomputational perspective (pp. 163-178). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

(2005). Chimerical colors: Some phenomenological predictions from cognitive neuroscience. Philosophical Psychology, 18 (5), 527-560. 10.1080/09515080500264115

Clark, A. (1985). Spectrum inversion and the color solid. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 23 (4), 431-443. 10.1111/j.2041-6962.1985.tb00413.x

Cohen, J. D. & Matthen, M. (Eds.) (2010). Color ontology and color science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Cohen, J. (2001). Color, content, and Fred: On a proposed reductio of the inverted spectrum hypothesis. Philosophical Studies, 103 (2), 121-144.

Cytowic, R. E. & Wood, F. B. (1982). Synesthesia: I. A review of major theories and their brain basis. Brain Cognition, 1 (1), 23-35. 10.1016/0278-2626(82)90004-5

Dennett, D. (1988). Quining qualia. In A. J. Marcel & E. Bisiach (Eds.) Consciousness in modern science (pp. 42-77). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

(1991). Consciousness explained. Boston, MA: Brown and Little.

Deroy, O. & Spence, C. (2013). Why we are not all synesthetes (not even weakly so). Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 20 (4), 643-664. 10.3758/s13423-013-0387-2

Deroy, O. (2013). Object-sensitivity versus cognitive penetrability of perception. Philosophical Studies, 162 (1), 87-107. 10.1007/s11098-012-9989-1

(2014). Modularity of perception. In M. Matthen (Ed.) Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Perception. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.. 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199600472.013.028

Descartes, R. (1984). Meditations on first philosophy; The philosophical writings of Descartes. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

Dixon, M. J., Smilek, D., Cudahy, C. & Merikle, P. M. (2000). Five plus two equals yellow. Nature, 406 (365). 10.1038/35019148

Fingerhut, J. (2011). Sensorimotor signature, skill, and synaesthesia. Two challenges for enactive theories of perception. In J. Fingerhut, S. Flach & J. Söffner (Eds.) Habitus in habitat III. Synaesthesia and kinaesthetics (pp. 101-120). Berne, GER: Peter Lang.

Fodor, J. (1983). The modularity of mind: An essay on faculty psychology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Frith, C. & Dolan, R. J. (1997). Brain mechanisms associated with top-down processes in perception. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London: Series B, Biological Sciences, 352 (1358), 1221-1230. 10.1098/rstb.1997.0104

Gertler, B. (2001). Introspecting phenomenal states. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 63 (2), 305-328. 10.2307/3071065

Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual perception. Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt.

Goldstone, R. L. (1998). Perceptual learning. Annual Review of Psychology, 49, 585-612. 10.1146/annurev.psych.49.1.585

Grush, R. (2007). A plug for generic phenomenology. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 30 (3), 504-505. 10.1017/S0140525X07002841

Grush, R., Jaswal, L., Knoepfler, J. & Brovold, A. (2015). Visual Adaptation to a Remapped Spectrum. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.) Open MIND. Frankfurt a. M., GER: MIND Group.

Hansen, T. & Gegenfurtner, K. R. (2006). Color scaling of discs and natural objects at different luminance levels. Visual Neuroscience, 23 (3-4), 603-610. 10.1017/S0952523806233121

Hansen, T., Olkkonen, M., Walter, S. & Gegenfurtner, K. R. (2006). Memory modulates color appearance. Nature Neuroscience, 9 (11), 1367-1368. 10.1038/nn1794

Hardin, C. L. (1993). Color for philosophers. Indianapolis, IN: Hacket.

Hawley, K. & Macpherson, F. (Eds.) (2011). The admissible contents of experience. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley-Blackwell.

Held, R. (1965). Plasticity in sensory-motor systems. Scientific American, 213 (5), 84-94.

Heuer, H. & Hegele, M. (2008). Constraints on visuo-motor adaptation depend on the type of visual feedback during practice. Experimental Brain Research, 185 (1), 101-110. 10.1007/s00221-007-1135-5

Heuer, H. & Rapp, K. (2011). Active error corrections enhance adaptation to a visuo-motor rotation. Experimental Brain Research, 211 (1), 97-108. 10.1007/s00221-011-2656-5

Hilbert, D. R. & Kalderon, M. E. (2000). Color and the inverted spectrum. In S. Davis (Ed.) Vancouver studies in cognitive science. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

Hohwy, J. (2011). Phenomenal variability and introspective reliability. Mind & Language, 26 (3), 261-286. 10.1111/j.1468-0017.2011.01418.x

Horgan, T. & Kriegel, U. (2007). Phenomenal epistemology: What is consciousness that we may know it so well? Philosophical Issues, 17 (1), 123-144. 10.1111/j.1533-6077.2007.00126.x

Horgan, T. & Tienson, J. (2002). Philosophy of mind: Classical and contemporary readings. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

Horgan, T., Tienson, J. & Graham, G. (2006). Internal-world skepticism and mental self-presentation. In U. Kriegel & K. Williford (Eds.) Self-representational approaches to consciousness (pp. 191-207). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Hubbard, E. M., Arman, A. C., Ramachandran, V. S. & Boynton, G. M. (2005). Individual differences among grapheme-colour synaesthetes: Brain-behavior correlations. Neuron, 45, 975-985. 10.1016/j.neuron.2005.02.008

Hume, D. (1978). A treatise of human nature. Oxford, UK: Clarendon.

Hupé, J. M., Bordier, C. & Dojat, M. (2012). The neural bases of grapheme-color synesthesia are not localized in real color-sensitive areas. Cerebral Cortex, 22, 1622-1633. 10.1093/cercor/bhr236

Hurlburt, R. T. & Schwitzgebel, E. (2007). Describing inner experience? Proponent meets skeptic. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Hurley, S. & Noë, A. (2003). Neural plasticity and consciousness. Biology & Philosophy, 18, 131-168.

Hurley, S. L. (1998). Consciousness in action. London, UK: Harvard University Press.

Husserl, E. (1982). Ideas. In T. E. Klein & W. E. Pohl (Eds.) Book I. Dordrecht, NL: Kluwer.

Kohler, I. (1962). Experiments with goggles. Scientific American, 5 (206), 62-72.

(1963). The formation and transformation of the perceptual world. Psychological Issues, 3 (4), 1-173.

Kriegel, U. (2002). Phenomenal content. Erkenntnis, 57 (2), 175-198.

(2007). Intentional inexistence and phenomenal intentionality. Philosophical Perspectives, 21 (1), 307-340. 10.1111/j.1520-8583.2007.00129.x

Levine, J. (1988). Absent and inverted qualia revisited. Mind and Language, 3 (4), 271-287. 10.1111/j.1468-0017.1988.tb00147.x

Lewis, C. (1929). Mind and the world order. New York, NY: Charles Scribner's Sons.

Locke, J. (1689/1979). An essay concerning human understanding. In P. H. Nidditch (Ed.) Clarendon edition. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.

Lupyan, G. (2015). Cognitive penetrability of perception in the age of prediction: Predictive systems are penetrable systems. Review of Philosophy and Psychology.

Machery, E. (2009). Doing without concepts. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

Macpherson, F. (2005). Colour inversion problems for representationalism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 70 (1), 127-152. 10.1111/j.1933-1592.2005.tb00508.x

(2012). Cognitive penetration of colour experience: Rethinking the issue in light of an indirect mechanism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 84 (1), 24-62. 10.1111/j.1933-1592.2010.00481.x

Marks, L. E. & Odgaard, E. C. (2005). Developmental constraints on theories of synesthesia. In C. Robertson & N. Sagiv (Eds.) Synesthesia: Perspectives from cognitive neuroscience (pp. 214-236). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

McCauley, R. N. & Henrich, J. (2006). Susceptibility to the Müller-Lyer illusion, theory-neutral observation, and the diachronic penetrability of the visual input system. Philosophical Psychology, 19 (1), 79-101. 10.1080/09515080500462347

McLaughlin, B. (2003). Color, consciousness, and color consciousness. New essays on consciousness (pp. 97-154). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

Meier, B. (2013). Semantic representation of synaesthesia. Theoria et Historia Scientiarum, 10, 125-134. 10.12775/ths-2013-0006

Metzinger, T. (2003a). Being no one: The self-model theory of subjectivity. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

(2003b). Phenomenal transparency and cognitive self-reference. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 2 (4), 353-393. 10.1023/B: PHEN.0000007366.42918.eb

(2014). How does the brain encode epistemic reliability? Perceptual presence, phenomenal transparency, and counterfactual richness. Cognitive Neuroscience, 5 (2), 122-124. 10.1080/17588928.2014.905519

Montague, M. & Bayne, T. (2011). Cognitive phenomenology: An introduction. In M. Montague & T. Bayne (Eds.) Cognitive phenomenology (pp. 1-34). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

Mossio, M. & Taraborelli, D. (2008). Action-dependent perceptual invariants: From ecological to sensorimotor approaches. Consciousness and Cognition, 17 (4), 1324-1340. 10.1016/j.concog.2007.12.003

Mroczko, A., Metzinger, T., Singer, W. & Nikolić, D. (2009). Immediate transfer of synesthesia to a novel inducer. Journal of Vision, 9 (25), 1-8. 10.1167/9.12.25

Mroczko-Wąsowicz, A. & Nikolić, D. (2013). Colored alphabets in bilingual synesthetes. Oxford Handbook of Synesthesia (pp. 165-180). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

(2014). Semantic mechanisms may be responsible for developing synesthesia. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 8 (509). 10.3389/fnhum.2014.00509

Mroczko-Wąsowicz, A. & Werning, M. (2012). Synesthesia, sensory-motor contingency and semantic emulation: How swimming style-color synesthesia challenges the traditional view of synesthesia. Frontiers in Psychology, 3 (279). 10.3389/fpsyg.2012.00279

Mroczko-Wąsowicz, A. (2013). The unity of consciousness and phenomenon of synesthesia [Die Einheit des Bewusstseins und das Phänomen der Synästhesie]. Published doctoral dissertation, Johannes Gutenberg University of Mainz.

Myin, E. (2001). Color and the duplication assumption. Synthese, 129 (1), 61-77. 10.1023/A:1012647207838

Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? The Philosophical Review, 83 (4), 435-450. 10.2307/2183914

Nanay, B. (2014). Cognitive penetration and the gallery of indiscernibles. Frontiers in Psychology, 5 (1527). 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.01527

Nelkin, N. (1989). Propositional attitudes and consciousness. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 49 (3), 413-430. 10.2307/2107796

Nida-Ruemelin, M. (1993). Farben und phänomenales Wissen. Eine Materialismuskritik. Conceptus-Studien 9. Wien, AUT: Verlag der wissenschaftlichen Gesellschaften Österreichs.

(1996). Pseudonormal vision. An actual case of qualia inversion? Philosophical Studies, 82 (2), 145-157.

Nikolić, D., Lichti, P. & Singer, W. (2007). Color opponency in synaesthetic experiences. Psychological Science, 18 (6), 481-486. 10.1111/j.1467-9280.2007.01925.x

Noguchi, Y., Inui, K. & Kakigi, R. (2004). Temporal dynamics of neural adaptation effect in the human visual ventral stream. The Journal of Neuroscience, 24 (28), 6283-6290. 10.1523/JNEUROSCI.0655-04.2004

Noë, A. (2005). Action in perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

(2012). Varieties of Presence. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

(2015). Concept pluralism, direct perception, and the fragility of presence. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.) Open MIND. Frankfurt a. M., GER: MIND Group.

O'Regan, J. K. & Noë, A. (2001). A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

O’Regan, J. K. (2011). Why red doesn't sound like a bell: Understanding the feel of consciousness. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

Peacocke, C. (1983). Sense and Content. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

Pitt, D. (2004). The phenomenology of cognition or what is it like to think that P? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 69 (1), 1-36. 10.1111/j.1933-1592.2004.tb 00382.x

Prinz, J. J. (2010). Can concept empiricism forestall eliminativism? Mind & Language, 25 (5), 5612-5621. 10.1111/j.1468-0017.2010.01404.x

(2012). The conscious brain. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

Proulx, M. J. & Störig, P. (2006). Seeing sounds and tingling tongues: Qualia in synaesthesia and sensory substitution. Anthropology & Philosophy, 7, 135-150.

Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1999). Is vision continuous with cognition? The case for cognitive impenetrability of visual perception. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22 (3), 341-365. 10.1017/s0140525x99002022

Raftopoulos, A. (2005). Cognitive penetrability of perception: A new perspective. Cognitive penetrability of perception: Attention, action, strategies, and bottom-up constraints (pp. 1-25). Hauppauge, NY: Nova Science.

(2009). Cognition and perception: How do psychology and the neural science inform philosophy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Ramachandran, V. S. & Hubbard, E. M. (2001a). Synaesthesia: A window into perception, thought and language. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8, 3-34.

(2001b). Psychophysical investigations into the neural basis of synaesthesia. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences, 268 (1470), 979-983. 10.1098/rspb.2000.1576

Ramachandran, V. S. & Rogers-Ramachandran, D. (1996). Synaesthesia in phantom limbs induced with mirrors. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences, 263 (1369), 377-386. 10.1098/rspb.1996.0058

Rees, G. & Frith, C. (2007). Methodologies for identifying the neural correlates of consciousness. In M. Velmans & S. Schneider (Eds.) The Blackwell companion to consciousness (pp. 553-566). Malden, MA: Blackwell.

Robinson, H. (1994). Perception. London, UK: Routledge.

Schwitzgebel, E. (2008). The unreliability of naïve introspection. The Philosophical Review, 117 (2), 245-273. 10.1215/00318108-2007-037

Seitz, A. & Watanabe, T. (2005). A unified model for perceptual learning. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 9 (7), 329-334. 10.1016/j.tics.2005.05.010

Seth, A. K. (2014). A predictive processing theory of sensorimotor contingencies: Explaining the puzzle of perceptual presence and its absence in synaesthesia. Cognitive Neuroscience, 5 (2), 97-118. 10.1080/17588928.2013.877880

(2015). The cybernetic Bayesian brain: From interoceptive inference to sensorimotor contingencies. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.) Open MIND. Frankfurt a. M., GER: MIND Group.

Shoemaker, S. (1982). The inverted spectrum. Journal of Philosophy, 79 (7), 357-381.

(1994). Phenomenal character. Noûs, 28 (1), 21-38. 10.2307/2215918

(2001). Introspection and phenomenal character. Philosophical Topics, 28 (2), 247-273. 10.5840/philtopics20002825

Siegel, S. (2006). Which properties are represented in perception? In T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.) Perceptual Experience (pp. 481-503). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

(2012). Cognitive penetrability and perceptual justification. Noûs, 46 (2), 201-222. 10.1111/j.1468-0068.2010.00786.x

Siewert, C. (1998). The significance of consciousness. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Simner, J. (2007). Beyond perception: Synaesthesia as a psycholinguistic phenomenon. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 11 (1), 23-29. 10.1016/j.tics.2006.10.010

(2012). Defining synaesthesia: A response to two excellent commentaries. British Journal of Psychology, 103 (1), 24-27. 10.1111/j.2044-8295.2011.02059.x

Smithson, H. E. (2005). Review. Sensory, computational and cognitive components of human color constancy. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, 360 (1458), 1329-1346. 10.1098/rstb.2005.1633

Stoerig, P. & Cowey, A. (1989). Wavelength sensitivity in blindsight. Nature, 342 (6252), 916-918. 10.1038/342916a0

(1991). Increment threshold spectral sensitivity in blindsight: Evidence for colour opponency. Brain, 114 (3), 1487-1512.

Stokes, D. (2012). Perceiving and desiring: A new look at the cognitive penetrability of experience. Philosophical Studies, 158 (3), 479-492. 10.1007/s11098-010-9688-8

Strawson, P. F. (1985). Causation and explanation. In B. Vermazen & J. Hintikka (Eds.) Essays on Davidson (pp. 115-135). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

(1994). Mental reality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Stroop, J. R. (1935). Studies of interference in serial verbal reactions. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 18 (6), 643-662. 10.1037/h0054651

Taraborelli, D. & Mossio, M. (2008). On the relation between the enactive and the sensorimotor approach to perception. Consciousness and Cognition, 17 (4), 1343-1344. 10.1016/j.concog.2008.08.002

Tye, M. (1993). Qualia, content, and the inverted spectrum. Noûs, 27 (2), 159-183. 10.2307/2216047

(1995). Ten problems of consciousness. Consciousness, color and content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

(2000). Consciousness, Color and Content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

van Leeuwen, T. M., Petersson, K. M. & Hagoort, P. (2010). Synaesthetic colour in the brain: Beyond colour areas. A functional magnetic resonance imaging study of synaesthetes and matched controls. PLoS ONE, 5, e12074.

Varela, F. J. (1996). Neurophenomenology: A methodological remedy for the hard problem. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 3 (4), 330-349.

Vetter, P. & Newen, A. (2014). Varieties of cognitive penetration in visual perception. Consciousness and Cognition, 27, 62-75. 10.1016/j.concog.2014.04.007

Vuilleumier, P. & Driver, J. (2007). Modulation of visual processing by attention and emotion: Windows on causal interactions between human brain regions. Philosophical transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B: Biological sciences, 362 (1481), 837-855. 10.1098/rstb.2007.2092

Ward, D. (2012). Why don’t synaesthetic colours adapt away? Philosophical Studies, 159 (1), 123-138. 10.1007/s11098-010-9693-y

Webster, M. A. (2012). Evolving concepts of sensory adaptation. F1000 Biology Reports, 4 (21). 10.3410/B4-21

Winawer, J., Witthoft, N., Frank, M. C., Wu, L., Wade, A. R. & Boroditsky, L. (2007). Russian blues reveal effects of language on color discrimination. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA, 104 (19), 7780-7785. 10.1073/pnas.0701644104

Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations. Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell.

Wu, W. (2013). Visual spatial constancy and modularity: Does intention penetrate vision? Philosophical Studies, 165, 647-669. 10.1007/s11098-012-9971-y

Zmigrod, S. & Hommel, B. (2011). The relationship between feature binding and consciousness: Evidence from asynchronous multi-modal stimuli. Consciousness and Cognition, 20 (3), 586-593. 10.1016/j.concog.2011.01.011