References

Adams, F. & Aizawa, K. (2010). Causal theories of mental content. The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Stanford, CA.

Begby, E. (2011). Review of origins of objectivity. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews

Block, N. (1983). The photographic fallacy in the debate about mental imagery. Noûs, 17 (4), 651-662.

(1995). On a confusion about a function of consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 18 (2), 227-247. 10.1017/S0140525X00038188

(2007a). Consciousness, accessibility, and the mesh between psychology and neuroscience. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 30 (5-6), 481-548. 10.1017/S0140525X07002786

(2007b). Overflow, access and attention. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 30 (5-6), 530-542. 10.1017/S0140525X07003111

(2008). Consciousness and cognitive access. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, CVIII (3), 289-317. 10.1016/j.neures.2009.09.1651

(2011). Perceptual consciousness overflows cognitive access. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 15 (12), 567-575. 10.1016/j.tics.2011.11.001

(2014a). Consciousness, big science and conceptual clarity. In G. Marcus & J. Freeman (Eds.) The future of the brain: Essays by the world's leading neuroscientists (pp. 161-176). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

(2014b). Rich conscious perception outside focal attention. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 18 (9), 445-447. 10.1016/j.tics.2014.05.007

(2014c). Seeing-as in the light of vision science. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 89 (3), 560-573. 10.1111/phpr.12135

(2015). Precision, acuity, veridicality and the nature of perception. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.) Open MIND (pp. 1-52). Frankfurt a. M., GER: MIND Group.

Bornstein, M. (1985). On the development of color naming in young children: Data and theory. Brain and Language, 26 (1), 72-93. 10.1016/0093-934X(85)90029-X

Bronfman, Z., Brezis, N., Jacobson, H. & Usher, M. (2014). We see more than we can report: "Cost free" color phenomenality outside focal attention. Psychological Science. 10.1177/0956797614532656

Burge, T. (2014). Reply to Block: Adaptation and the upper border of perception. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 89 (3), 573-583. 10.1111/phpr.12136

Butler, A., Oruc, I., Fox, C. J. & Barton, J. J. S. (2008). Factors contributing to the adaptation aftereffects of facial expression. Brain Research, 1191, 116-126. 10.1016/j.brainres.2007.10.101

Byrne, A., Hilbert, D. R. & Siegel, S. (2007). Do we see more than we can access? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 30 (5-6), 501-502. 10.1017/S0140525X07002816

Campbell, J. (2014). Experiencing objects as mind-independennt. In J. Campbell & Q. Cassam (Eds.) Berkeley's puzzle: What does experience teach us? (pp. 50-74). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

Fink, S. B. (2015). Phenomenal precision and some possible pitfalls: A commentary on Ned Block. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.) Open MIND (pp. 1-14). Frankfurt a. M., GER: MIND Group.

Fodor, J. A. (1987). Psychosemantics: The problem of meaning in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Freeman, J. & Pelli, D. (2007). An escape from crowding. Journal of Vision, 7 (2), 1-14. 10.1167/7.2.22

Grush, R. (2007). A plug for generic phenomenology. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 30 (5-6), 504-505. 10.1017/S0140525X07002841

Jacobson, H. & Putnam, H. (forthcoming). Against perceptual conceptualism. International Journal of Philosophical Studies

Jacobson, H. (2014). Phenomenal consciousness, representational contentand cognitive access: a missing link between two debates. Phenomenology and Cognitive Science, 1-15. 10.1007/s11097-014-9399-2

Kouider, S., de Gardelle, V. & Dupoux, E. (2007). Partial awareness and the illusion of phenomenal consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 30 (5-6), 510-511. 10.1017/S0140525X07002919

Lamme, V. (2003). Why visual attention and awareness are different. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7 (1), 12-18. 10.1016/S1364-6613(02)00013-X

Morrison, J. (2015). Anti-atomism about color representation. Noûs, 49 (1), 94-122. 10.1111/nous.12018

Papineau, D. (2007). Reuniting (scene) phenomenology with (scene) access. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 30 (5-6), 521-521. 10.1017/S0140525X07003019

Phillips, I. B. (2011). Perception and iconic memory: What Sperling doesn't show. Mind & Language, 26 (4), 381-411. 10.1111/j.1468-0017.2011.01422.x

Siegel, S. (2010). The contents of visual experience. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

Sligte, I. G., Scholte, H. S. & Lamme, V. (2008). Are there multiple visual short term memory stores? Plos One, 3 (2), e1699-e1699. 10.1371/journal.pone.0001699

Sligte, I. G., Vandenbroucke, A. R. E., Scholte, H. S. & Lamme, V. (2010). Detailed sensory memory, sloppy working memory. Frontiers in Psychology, 1, 1-10. 10.3389/fpsyg.2010.00175

Sligte, I. G., Wokke, M. E., Tesselaar, J. P., Scholte, H. S. & Lamme, V. (2011). Magnetic stimulation of the dorsolateral prefrontal cortex dissociates fragile visual short tem memory from visual working memory. Neuropsychologia, 49 (6), 1578-1588. 10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2010.12.010

Sperling, G. (1960). The information available in brief visual presentations. Psychological Monographs, 74 (498), 1-29.

Stazicker, J. (2011). Attention, visual consciousness and indeterminacy. Mind & Language, 26 (2), 156-184. 10.1111/j.1468-0017.2011.01414.x

(forthcoming). The visual presence of determinable properties. In F. Dorsch, F. Macpherson & M. Nida-Rümelin (Eds.) Phenomenal Presence. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

Van Gulick, R. (2007). What if phenomenal consciousness admits of degrees? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 30 (5-6), 528-529. 10.1017/S0140525X07003093

Vandenbroucke, A. R. E., Sligte, I. G. & Lamme, V. (2011). Manipulations of attention dissociate fragile visual short term memory from visual working memory. Neuropsychologia, 49 (6), 1559-1568. 10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2010.12.044