References

Bechtel, W. (1985). Realism, instrumentalism, and the Intentional Stance. Cognitive Science, 9 (4), 473-497. 10.1207/s15516709cog0904_5

Blanke, O. & Metzinger, T. (2009). Full-body illusions and minimal phenomenal selfhood. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 13 (1), 7-13. 10.1016/j.tics.2008.10.003

Botvinick, M. & Cohen, J. (1998). Rubber hands "feel" touch that eyes see. Nature, 391 (756). 10.1038/35784

Clark, A. (1996). Linguistic anchors in the sea of thoughts. Pragmatics & Cognition, 4 (1), 93-103. 10.1075/pc.4.1.09cla

(2013). Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36 (3), 181-204. 10.1017/S0140525X12000477

(2015). Embodied prediction. In T. Metzinger & J. W. Windt (Eds.) Open MIND. Frankfurt a. M., GER: MIND Group.

Dennett, D. C. (1971). Intentional systems. Journal of Philosophy, 68, 87-106.

(1984). Elbow room. The varieties of free will worth wanting. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.

(1987). The Intentional Stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

(1991). Consciousness explained. New York, NY: Back Bay Books/Little, Brown and Company.

(1994). The Role of Language in Intelligence. In J. Khalfa (Ed.) What is Intelligence? The Darwin College Lectures. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.. 10.1075/pc.4.1.09cla

(1995). Darwin’s dangerous idea: Evolution and the meanings of life. New York, NY: Simon Schuster Paperbacks.

(1998a). Self-portrait. Brainchildren: Essays on designing minds (pp. 355-366). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

(1998b). Real patterns. Brainchildren: Essays on designing minds (pp. 95-120). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

(1999). The zombic hunch: Extinction of an intuition. Royal Institute of Philosophy Millennial Lecture

(2000). With a little help from my friends. In D. Ross, A. Brooks & D. Thompson (Eds.) Dennett’s Philosophy: A Comprehensive Assessment (pp. 327-388). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

(2004). Freedom Evolves. London, UK: Penguin Books.

(2005). Sweet dreams: Philosophical obstacles to a science of consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

(2006). Breaking the spell. Religion as a natural phenomenon. New York, NY: Penguin.

(2009). Intentional Systems Theory. In B. P. McLaughlin, A. Beckermann & S. Walter (Eds.) The Oxford handbook of philosophy of mind (pp. 339-349). Oxford, UK: Oxford Handbooks Online.

(2010). The evolution of why. In B. Weiss & J. Wanderer (Eds.) Reading Brandom: On making it explicit (pp. 48-62). New York, NY: Routledge.

(2013a). Intuition pumps and other tools for thinking. New York, NY: W. W. Norton & Co..

(2013b). Expecting ourselves to expect: The Bayesian brain as a projector. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36 (3), 29-30. 10.1017/S0140525X12002208

(2015). Why and how does consciounsess seem the way it seems? In T. Metzinger & J. W. Windt (Eds.) Open MIND. Frankfurt a. M., GER: MIND Group.

Friston, K., Mattout, J. & Kilner, J. (2011). Action understanding and active inference. Biological Cybernetics, 104 (1-2), 137-160. 10.1007/s00422-011-0424-z

Friston, K. J., Shiner, T., FitzGerald, T., Galea, J. M., Adams, R., Brown, H., Dolan, R. J., Moran, R., Stephan, K. E. & Bestmann, S. (2012). Dopamine, affordance and active inference. PLoS Computational Biology, 8 (1), e1002327-e1002327. 10.1371/journal.pcbi.1002327

Gibson, J. J. (1986). The ecological approach to visual perception. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

Harkness, D. (2015). From explanatory ambition to explanatory power-A commentary on Jakob Hohwy. In T. Metzinger & J. W. Windt (Eds.) Open MIND. Frankfurt a. M., GER: MIND Group.

Hohwy, J. (2013). The predictive mind. Oxford, UK: Oxford Univeristy Press.

(2014). The self-evidencing brain. Noûs, online. 10.1111/nous.12062

(2015). The neural organ explains the mind. In T. Metzinger & J. W. Windt (Eds.) Open MIND. Frankfurt a. M., GER: MIND Group.

Hohwy, J., Ropstorff, A. & Friston, K. (2008). Predictive coding explains binocular rivalry: An epistemological review. Cognition, 108 (3), 687-701. 10.1016/j.cognition.2008.05.010

Hume, D. (1995). An inquiry concerning human understanding. London, UK: Pearson.

Humphrey, N. (1983). Consciousness regained. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

Lurz, R. W. (2010). Belief attribution in animals: On how to move forward conceptually and empirically. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 2 (1), 19-59. 10.1007/s13164-010-0042-z

Madary, M. (2015). Extending the explanandum for predictive processing-A commentary on Andy Clark. In T. Metzinger & J. W. Windt (Eds.) Open MIND. Frankfurt a. M., GER: MIND Group.

Marticorena, D. C.W., Ruiz, A. M., Mukerji, C., Goddu, A. & Santos, L. R. (2011). Monkeys represent others’ knowledge but not their beliefs. Developmental Science, 14 (6), 1467-7687. 10.1111/j.1467-7687.2011.01085.x

McKay, R. T. & Dennett, D. C. (2009). The evolution of misbelief. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 32, 493-561. 10.1017 / S0140525X09990975

Metzinger, T. (2003). Being no one. The self-model theory of subjectivity. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Roskies, A. (2015). Davidson on believers: Can non-linguistic creatures have propositional attitudes? In T. Metzinger & J. W. Windt (Eds.) Open MIND. Frankfurt a. M., GER: MIND Group.

Sellars, W. (1963). Science, perception and reality. London, UK: Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd..

Seth, A. (2015). The cybernetic bayesian brain: From interoceptive inference to sensorimotor contingencies. In T. Metzinger & J. W. Windt (Eds.) Open MIND. Frankfurt a. M., GER: MIND Group.

Stevens, G. C. (1989). The latitudinal gradients in geographical range: How so many species co-exist in the tropics. American Naturalist, 133 (2), 240-256.

Tye, M. (2013). Qualia. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2013 Edition)

Wiese, W. (2015). Perceptual presence in the Kuhnian-Popperian Bayesian brain—A commentary on Anil Seth. In T. Metzinger & J. W. Windt (Eds.) Open MIND. Frankfurt a. M., GER: MIND Group.

Yu, P. & Fuller, G. (1986). A critique of Dennett. Synthese, 66 (3), 453-476. 10.1007/BF00414062