References

Armstrong, D. M. (1980). The nature of mind and other essays. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

Banks, M. S., Sekuler, A. B. & Anderson, S. J. (1991). Peripheral spatial vision: Limits imposed by optics, photoreceptors, and receptor pooling. Journal of the Optical Society of America A, 8 (11), 1775-1787. 10.1364/JOSAA.8.001775

Bayne, T. (2010). The unity of consciousness. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

Block, N. (1991). Troubles with functionalism. In David Rosenthal (Ed.) The nature of mind (pp. 211-228). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

(1996). Mental paint and mental latex. Philosophical Issues, 7, 19-49. 10.2307/1522889

(1997). On a confusion about the function of consciousness. In N. Block, O. Flanagan and G. Güzeldere (Eds.) The nature of consciousness: Philosophical debates (pp. 375-415). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

(2007). Consciousness, accessibility, and the mesh between psychology and neuroscience. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 30 (5-6), 481-548. 10.1017/S0140525X07002786

(2015). The puzzle of perceptual precision. In T. Metzinger and J. M. Windt (Eds.) Open MIND. Frankfurt a. M., GER: MIND Group.

(forthcoming 2015). The Canberra Plan neglects ground. In T. Hogan, M. Sabates and D. Sosa (Eds.) Qualia and mental causation in a physical world: Themes from the philosophy of Jaegwon Kim. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/faculty/block/papers/Kimfestschrift.pdf

Boring, E. (1953). The history of introspection. Psychological Bulletin, 50 (3), 169-189. 10.1037/h0090793

Brentano, F. (1874). Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt. Leipzig, GER: Duncker & Humblot.

Burge, T. (2010). Origins of objectivity. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

Carney, T., Tyler, C. W., Watson, A. B., Makous, W., Beutter, B., Chen, C.-C., Norcia, A. M. & Klein, S. (2000). Modelfest first year results and plans for year two. In B. E. Rogowitz and T. N. Pappas (Eds.) Human vision and electronic imaging V (pp. 140-151). The International Society for Optical Engineering.

Carrasco, M., Ling, S. & Read, S. (2004). Attention alters appearance. Nature Neuroscience, 7 (3), 308-313. 10.1038/nn1194

Chalmers, D. J. (2011). Verbal disputes. Philosophical Review, 120 (4), 515-566. 10.1215/00318108-1334478

Churchland, P. M. (1985). Reduction, qualia, and the direct introspection of brain states. The Journal of Philosophy, 82 (1), 8-28.

(2005). Chimerical colors: Some phenomenological predictions from cognitive neuroscience. Philosophical Psychology, 18 (5), 527-560.

Craver, C. F. (2007). Explaining the brain: Mechanisms and the mosaic unity of neuroscience. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

Fechner, G. T. (1860). Elemente der Psychophysik. Leipzig, GER: Breitkopf & Härtel.

Goldman, Alvin I. (2006). Simulating minds. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

Gombrich, E. (1982/2002). The visual image. The image and the eye: Further studies in the psychology of pictorial representation (pp. 137-161). London & New York: Phaidon.

Grush, R. (2007). A plug for generic phenomenology. Brain and Behavioral Sciences, 30 (5/6), 504-505. 10.1017/S0140525X07002841

Hardy, J. D., Wolff, H. G. & Goodel, H. (1952). Pain sensations and reactions. New York, NY: Hafner.

Hardy, J. D., Wolff, H. G. & Goodell, H. (1940). Studies on pain. A new method for measuring pain threshold: Observations on spatial summation of pain. The Journal of Clinical Investigation, 19 (4), 649-657. 10.1172/JCI101168

Haugeland, J. (1981). Analog and analog. Philosophical Topics, 12 (1), 213-225.

Jackson, A. S. (1960). Analog computation. New York, NY: McGraw-Hill.

James, W. (1890/1957). The Principles of Psychology.

Jäkel, F. & Wichmann, F. A. (2006). Spatial four-alternative forced-choice method is the preferred psychophysical method for naïve observers. Journal of Vision, 6 (11), 1307-1322. 10.1167/6.11.13

Kant, I. (1787/2008). Kritik der reinen Vernunft. Essen, GER: Korpora.

Kosslyn, S. M. (1980). Image and mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Lewis, D. (1971). Analog and digital. Nôus, 5 (3), 321-327.

Locke, John (1690/2008). An essay concerning human understanding. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

Lycan, W. G. (1996). Consciousness and experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Nanay, B. (2005). Is twofoldness necessary for representational seeing? British Journal of Aesthetics, 45 (3), 248-257. 10.1093/aesthj/ayi034

Pelli, D. G. & Bex, P. (2013). Measuring contrast sensitivity. Vision Research, 90 (0), 10 - 14. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.visres.2013.04.015. http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0042698913001132

Schindler, S. (2013). Mechanistic explanation: Asymmetry lost. In D. Dieks & V. Karakostas (Eds.) Recent Progress in Philosophy of Science: perspectives and foundational problems. Dordrecht, NL: Springer. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/9557/1/Craver_symmetry_final.pdf

Sperling, G. (1960). The information available in brief visual presentations. Psychological Monographs: General and Applied, 74 (498), 1-29. 10.1037/h0093759

Wiese, W. & Metzinger, T. (2012). Desiderata for a mereotopological theory of consciousness. In S. Edelman, T. Fekete and N. Zach (Eds.) Being in time: Dynamical models of phenomenal experience (pp. 185-209). Amsterdam, NL: John Benjamins.

Williamson, T. (1990). Identity and discrimination. Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

Wollheim, R. (1987). Painting as an art. Thames & Hudson Ltd.