References

Akins, K. (1996). Of sensory systems and the “aboutness” of mental states. Journal of Philosophy, 93 (7), 337-372. 10.2307/2941125

Anscombe, G. E. M. (1957). Intention. Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell.

Atmanspacher, H. & beim Graben, P. (2007). Contextual emergence of mental states from neurodynamics. Chaos and Complexity Letters, 2 (2-3), 151-168.

Bernet, R., Kern, I. & Marbach, E. (1993). An introduction to Husserlian phenomenology. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

Brockman, J. (1996). Third culture: Beyond the scientific revolution. New York, NY: Touchstone.

Chalmers, D. (1996). The conscious mind. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

Churchland, P. M. (1981). Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes. Journal of Philosophy, 78 (2), 67-90. 10.1111/j.1467-9973.1992.tb00550.x

Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body, and world together again. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

(2013). Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Science, 36 (3), 1-73. 10.1017/S0140525X12000477

(2015). Embodied Prediction. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.) Open MIND. Frankfurt a.M., GER: MIND Group.

Dale, R. & Spivey, M. (2005). From apples and oranges to symbolic dynamics: A framework for conciliating notions of cognitive representation. Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence, 17 (4), 317-342. 10.1080/09528130500283766

Davidson, D. (1963). Actions, reasons and causes. Journal of Philosophy, 60 (23), 685-700. 10.2307/2023177

Dennett, D. (1991). Consciousness explained. Boston, MA: Little, Brown, & Co.

Dixon, J., Kelty-Stephen, D. & Anastas, J. (2014). The embodied dynamics of problem solving: New structure from multiscale interactions. In L. Shapiro (Ed.) The Routledge handbook of embodied cognition. London, UK: Routledge.

Dretske, F. (1995). Naturalizing the mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Fischer, J. M. & Ravizza, M. (1998). Responsibility and control: A theory of moral responsibility. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

Fodor, J. (1987). Psychosemantics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Freeman, J. & Simoncelli, E. (2011). Metamers of the ventral stream. 10.1038/nn.2889

Friston, K. (2005). A theory of cortical responses. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 360 (1456), 815-836. 10.1098/rstb.2005.1622

(2008). Hierarchical models in the brain. PloS Comput Biol, 4 (11), e1000211. 10.1371/journal.pcbi.1000211

(2010). The free-energy principle: A unified brain theory? Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 11 (2), 127-138. 10.1038/nrn2787

(2013). Life as we know it. Journal of the Royal Society Interface, 10 (86), 1-12. 10.1098/rsif.2013.0475

Friston, K., Kilner, J. & Harrison, L. (2006). A free energy principle for the brain. Journal of Physiology - Paris, 100, 70-87. 10.1016/j.jphysparis.2006.10.001

Gregory, R. (1980). Perceptions as hypotheses. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 290 (1038), 181-197.

Haynie, D. (2008). Biological thermodynamics. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

Hinton, G. (2007). Learning multiple layers of representation. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 11 (10), 428-34. 10.1016/j.tics.2007.09.004

Hohwy, J. (2013). The predictive mind. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

(2014). The self-evidencing brain. Noûs, 1-27. 10.1111/nous.12062

Hopp, W. (2011). Perception and knowledge: A phenomenological account. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

Hume, D. (1993). An enquiry concerning human understanding. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing.

Husserl, E. (1900). Logische Untersuchungen. London, UK: Routledge.

(1966). Husserliana XI Analysen zur passiven Synthesis. Dordrecht, NL: Kluwer.

(1969). Husserliana X zur Phänomenologie des inneren Zeitbewusstseins (1893-1917). Dordrecht, NL: Kluwer.

(1973). Husserliana XVI Ding und Raum: Vorlesungen 1907. Dordrecht, NL: Kluwer.

Jackendoff, R. (1987). Consciousness and the computational mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Jacob, P. (2010). Intentionality. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Fall. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/intentionality/

Kant, I. (1998). Kritik der reinen Vernunft. Hamburg, GER: Meiner Verlag.

Levy, N. (2012). Ecological engineering: Reshaping our environments to achieve our goals. Philosophy and Technology, 25 (4), 589-604.

Lewis, D. (1980). Veridical hallucination and prosthetic vision. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 58 (3), 239-249. 10.1080/00048408012341251

Madary, M. (2012a). Husserl on Perceptual Constancy. European Journal of Philosophy, 20 (1), 145-165. 10.1111/j.1468-0378.2010.00405.x

(2012b). How would the world look if it looked as if it were encoded as an intertwined set of probability density distributions? Frontiers in Psychology, 3. 10.3389/fpsyg.2012.00419

(2013). Anticipation and variation in visual content. Philosophical Studies, 165, 335-347. 10.1007/s11098-012-9926-3

Marr, D. (1982). Vision: A computational approach. New York, NY: Freeman and Co.

Maturana, H. R. & Varela, F. J. (1980). Autopoiesis and cognition: The realization of the living. Dordrecht, NL: Reidel.

McKenna, M. (2012). Conversation and responsibility. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

Menary, R. (2010). Cognitive integration and the extended mind. In R. Menary (Ed.) The extended mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962). Phenomenology of perception. London, UK: Routledge.

Metzinger, T. & Gallese, V. (2003). The emergence of a shared action ontology: Building blocks for a theory. Consciousness and Cognition, 12 (4), 549-571. 10.1016/S1053-8100(03)00072-2

Metzinger, T. (2003). Being no one: The self-model theory of subjectivity. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

(2009). The ego tunnel. New York, NY: Basic Books.

Millikan, R. (1984). Language, thought and other biological objects. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

(1995). Pushmi-pullyu representations. In J. Tomberlin (Ed.) Philosophical perspectives 9: AI, connectionism, and philosophical psychology. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing Company.

(2004). Varieties of meaning: The 2002 Jean-Nicod Lectures. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review, 83 (4), 435-450.

Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

O'Regan, K. & Noë, A. (2001). A sensorimotor approach to vision and visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24, 939-973.

Prinz, J. (2012). The conscious brain: How attention engenders experience. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

Rowlands, M. (2010). The new science of the mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Searle, J. (1983). Intentionality: An essay in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

Seth, A. (2014). A predictive processing theory of sensorimotor contingengies: Explaining the puzzle of perceptual presence and its absence in synesthesia. Cognitive Neuroscience, 5 (2), 97-118. 10.1080/17588928.2013.877880

Snow, C. P. (1959). The two cultures. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

Spivey, M. (2007). The continuity of mind. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

Spratling, M. (2013). Distinguishing theory from implementation in predictive coding accounts of brain function. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36 (3), 51-52. 10.1017/S0140525X12002178

Strawson, P. F. (1962). Freedom and Resentment. Proceedings of the British Academy, 48, 1-25.

Sunstein, C. (2014). Why nudge?: The politics of libertarian paternalism. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

Thaler, R. & Sunstein, C. (2008). Nudge: Improving decisions about health, wealth, and happiness. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Tye, M. (2000). Consciousness, color, and content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

von Helmholtz, H. (1867). Handbuch der Physiologischen Optik. Leipzig, GER: Leopold Voss.

von Uexküll, J. (1934). A stroll through the worlds of animals and men. In K. Lashley (Ed.) Instinctive behavior. New York, NY: International Universities Press.